Kaldor-Hicks criteria in a production economy:
The Kaldor-Hicks criteria in a production economy can be explained through the GUPF and the various allocation possibilities within them. Thus, an allocation is superior to another if it is possible that the winners compensate the losers for moving to the former (Kaldor) or if the losers bribe the winners not to move to the former (Hicks). In a production context, there are now two
forms of the Kaldor criteria:
- The strong Kaldor criteria requires any compensations to be a lump-sum transfer between individuals and thus, by not allowing production to change as part of the compensation, one is confined to making transfers within a given UPF;
- The weak Kaldor criterion allows production to change as part of the compensation, and thereby the entire GUPF is available.
It is clear that the weak Kaldor criteria can compare all Pareto-sub-optimal points in the GUPF. However, the strong criteria cannot do so. This is the complication that Kaldor criteria bring in a production economy. This is explained in the Figure below. As shown in the figure, there are two Utility Possibility Frontiers (UPF's).
Suppose we want to compare points E and G. Obviously, E is Pareto- inferior to F and G is Pareto-inferior to D, but it is not possible to compare E and G by the Pareto criterion. Let us then employ the strong Kaldor compensation test: if we move from point E to point G, it is obvious that individual B is the winner and individual A the loser, However, B can (hypothetically) compensate A for her loss and still remain better off by offering a compensation that takes the allocation to point H (note that both G and H are on the same frontier, UPFF - this is the requirement of the strong Kaldor criteria). At H, individual A would be at her old utility level, uA(E), but individual B would have utility uB(H) > uB(E). Thus she is strictly better off and by the Kaldor compensation criteria allocation G is superior to allocation E.
However, suppose we begin at G and want to move towards E. This implies that Individual A is now the winner and B the loser. Yet, individual A can hypothetically compensate individual B by offering a transfer payment that takes the allocation to point K. At K, individual B stays at her old utility level uB(G), but individual A improves her utility position from uA(G) to uB(K).
Thus, by the strong Kaldor compensation criteria, E is superior to G. And by the same criteria, G is superior to E. Thus points E and G are not consistently comparable.