Kaldor-Hicks Criteria:
Let us consider the Edgeworth-Bowley box as shown in Figure below. It is evident that allocations D and F (and indeed, all allocations in the "lens" formed by uA(E) and uB(E)) are Pareto-superior to E, but allocation C cannot be compared to either D, F or E.
An alternative criterion of judging whether an allocation was "preferable" to another was proposed by Nicholas Kaldor in his article, 'Welfare Propositions of Economics and Interpersonal Comparison of Utility', published in The Economic Journal, September, 1939. According to Kaldor's welfare criterion, if a certain change in economic organisation or policy makes some people better off and others worse off, then that change will increase social welfare, if those who gain from the reorganisation could compensate the losers and still be better off than before. In other words, Kaldor argued that an allocation is preferred to another if by moving from the second to the first, the "gainer" from the move can, by a lump-sum transfer, compensate the "loser" for her loss of utility and still make a gain in utility for herself. Hicks stated that, 'ifA is made so much better by the change that he could compensate B for his loss and still have something left over, then the reorganisation is unequivocal improvement'. To put it in other way, a change is an improvement if the losers in the changed situation cannot profitably bribe the gainers not to change from the original situation. Hicks has given his criterion from the loser's point of view, while Kaldor had formulated this criterion from the gainer's point of view. Thus, the two criteria are really the same though they are exposited
differently. That is why they are generally called by a single name, 'Kaldor- Hicks Compensation Criteria'.
Suppose we want to reorganise the allocation by moving from allocation E to allocation C. This shows that, individual A gains in utility (from uA(E) to uA(c)) and individual B loses (from uA(E) to uB(C)). This implies that, E and C are not Pareto-comparable. However, if we move to allocation C, individual A can pay individual B a portion of her gains so as to keep individual B at her old utility level uA(E). For instance, A can pay B the amount XAC - XAF (thus she moves to point F) so that B retains the same old utility level uB (E) while the utility of A is now uA(F). As the utility of A at allocation C is greater than that at F, (XAC - XAF), individual A makes a net gain XAC > XAF plus whatever she gained in terms of good Y. Thus, as shown in the figure when uA(F)> uA(E) it is worthwhile for her to propose moving to C and then paying individual A the amount XAC > XAF, thereby moving the economy to F.
Now, if the Kaldor compensation criteria implied merely that we moved from E to F, then it is not an improvement on the Pareto criterion as F is obviously Pareto-superior to E. However, Kaldor's innovation is to propose that allocation C is superior to that of E because it is possible for A to compensate B and still be better off. The crucial point is that A can compensate B, and not that A will compensate B. Thus, the move from E to C is actual, but the move from C to F is only hypothetical. Thus, Kaldor proposed that we can compare Pareto-incomparable points via the "hypothetical cornpernation" test. In sum, an allocation is preferable to another if it is possible to hypothetically redistribute goods so that a Pareto-improvement occurs.